CLCWeb: Comparative
Literature and Culture: A WWWeb Journal ISSN
1481-4374
CLCWeb Library of Research and Information ...
CLCWeb Contents 1.3 (June
1999)
<http://clcwebjournal.lib.purdue.edu/clcweb99-3/welfing99.html> © Purdue
University Press
Johannes F. WELFING
Author's Profile: Johannes Welfing received his Ph.D. in comparative
literature from the University of Alberta in 1999. For his dissertation -- entitled Nietzschean Configurations -- he received
a DAAD (Germany) fellowship to conduct research at the University in Siegen
(1997-98). Welfing has published on Nietzsche in LUMIS-Schriften (1998) and
in Slavica (1999) and on film in Studia Humanitas: Studies in Film
and Popular Culture (1999). Recently, Welfing accepted a term position in
French at the University of Lethbridge.
Nietzsche and the Knowledge of the Child at Play: On the
Question of Metaphysics
1. There is no consensus in Nietzsche criticism. In fact,
the views on Nietzsche are not just simply divergent but often diametrically
opposed. The contentious issue is often metaphysics or his belief in essence.
For some critics Nietzsche is just one thinker among the many, while for others
he is the first true philosopher. This polarization of opinions raises some
interesting questions about Nietzsche's philosophy: why is it that controversy
continues on whether Nietzsche believed in essence or on whether he attempted
to define existence? Or even beyond the question of metaphysics: why are the
opinions so polarized?
2. It is possible to establish a classification of Nietzsche
critics based on the question of metaphysical adherence. For some critics his
philosophy centres around one unifying idea, while for others this centralizing
unity is not just lacking, but precisely something Nietzsche never intended
to achieve. For some he remains a seeker of truth, while for others he offers
a clear set of premises to overcome the need for universal truths. The least
one can say at this stage is that Nietzsche's philosophy lacks clarity at crucial
points, and that it somehow offers room for this collection of rigorously dissenting
views. Thomas Mann, for instance, in his Nietzsches Philosophie im Lichte
unserer Erfahrung, speaks of Nietzsche's philosophy as being conditioned
by "einem einzigen, alles durchdringenden Grundgedanken," and of Nietzsche himself
as an aphorist without centre (45). David Allison <http://www.sunysb.edu/philosophy/faculty/allison/dallison.htm>,
however, in his preface to The New Nietzsche, argues for pretty much
the opposite: "[Nietzsche's] use of metaphor, aphorism, apothegm, styled ambiguity
all stands apart from the very system of Western thought that demands specific
unity and identification. The text of Nietzsche no longer is constrained to
a foundation of univocal meaning, discrete cause, unifying origin, to the principle
of identity and specific difference" (xxiv). Another set of difficulties follows
from this ambivalence in Nietzsche criticism, namely the difficulty of defining
metaphysics itself. A clear definition is often lacking in those interpreting
Nietzsche's work, and this creates additional problems exactly where the question
of a successful transcendence is raised. Heidegger <http://www.webcom.com/paf/ereignis.html> defines the concept of metaphysics as the forgetting of being with a capital
B (or, to be more precise, as Ando Takatura in his Metaphysics: A Critical
Survey of its Meaning explains, the forgetting of the "'to be' of being,
or the inquiring into the 'to be' qua 'to be'" (104)). Metaphysical longing
is defined in terms of nostalgia for essence and substance beyond the "to be" of being itself. Herman Berger, however, in a more recent study entitled Wat
is Metafysica: een studie over transcendentie, argues for a different understanding
of the concept of metaphysics, one that according to Berger is closer to Aristotle's
original definition of the term, and which does not separate (or forgets to
separate): "das Sein" from "das Seiende," precisely because it focuses on "das
Sein" in relation to "das Seiende" (41).
3. Yet another question is that of the possibility of escaping
or going beyond metaphysics itself. The concept of doing without essence has
had a strange attraction for many thinkers -- it certainly fascinated Nietzsche
-- and it will perhaps always continue to do so. In the following, I will attempt
to address some of these questions. I intend to demonstrate that it is extremely
difficult to provide any conclusive answers to the question of Nietzsche's antimetaphysical
stance and that any attempt at doing so can be undermined in a relatively easy
fashion. The starting point in this article will be that Nietzsche's philosophy
is ambiguous on the question of metaphysics, and that it is this essential ambiguity
which causes the controversy to continue. My task is not to condemn any of the
existing Nietzsche camps, but rather to investigate the reasons why this polarization
of opinions has taken place -- and still is -- in Nietzsche interpretation today.
To prove this, we need only refer to works such as Nietzsche as Postmodernist:
Essays pro and contra (see Koelb), which is a collection of interpretations
behind which looms the dark cloud of the metaphysical question. As the title
indicates, the choice is either for or against, within or beyond metaphysics.
Similarly, my study, too, will be a dialogue with interpreters and critics such
as Paul de Man, Alan Schrift, and others for whom Nietzsche' work means theory
beyond metaphysics. I will investigate the paradigm of the child at play in
the sand and attempt to demonstrate that this metaphor speaks much less definitively
in favour of freedom from metaphysics than contemporary thinkers would have
us believe.
4. My approach in this article is based theoretically background
in philosophy and comparative literary theory: Nietzsche is an intellectual
authority who is approached from all kinds of literary and cultural angles and
writers, philosophers and critics from all over the world have commented on
his writing. Nietzsche's writing may be there, solidified on paper, yet the
interpretations are constantly changing. In this article, I will focus on Nietzsche
and the metaphysical tradition and on how different authorities, belonging to
different cultural and literary traditions, have interpreted and explained the
question of metaphysics in relation to Nietzsche.
The Difficulty of Understanding Metaphysics and The Question
of a Successful Transcendence
5. Contemporary Nietzsche interpretation centres around one
complex yet basic problem --that of metaphysics. To what extent are we to consider
Nietzsche as a philosopher who not only attempted to escape the constraints
of traditional metaphysics, but who actually succeeded in doing this? Who believed
that metaphysics, with whatever nuance in meaning one would define this, was
something that could be conquered or transcended (the term transcendence may
be inappropriate here since, if anything, Nietzsche's project of liberating
himself from metaphysics is directed against any form of transcendence in the
traditional sense of the word). Perhaps one should argue that Nietzsche's stand
is more skeptical and reserved. Is the real tragedy of his writing not so much
the end of religious transcendence as the realization in his heart of hearts
that escaping metaphysics proper is impossible, and that any attempt at doing
so is ultimately an act of self-deception and misplaced human arrogance? Are
human beings inherently religious, the concept of religion being more subtly
defined here as a constellation of metaphysically preestablished particulars
that constitute the human mind and body and presuppose its working? Can one
survive a life without meaning, essence, or a perception of the self as a unified
entity, while at the same time giving in to a playful economy of truth alternating
with lie? In other words, does the Nietzschean infant truly escape metaphysics
in that it enjoys both the creation and destruction of the sand castle it has
built, or has the child only imagined that it does?
6. Nietzsche may criticize the metaphysical tradition, yet
it remains to be established what exactly is being proposed to overcome it,
and how convincingly this is done. Heidegger's claim of Nietzsche's adherence
to a full-fledged metaphysical tradition often stands as a point of reference:
Nietzsche may have attempted to escape the tradition, yet because of the rigour
of the attempt itself, he entrenches himself even deeper in the metaphysical
swamp of essence. Heidegger, while defining metaphysics in terms of essence
("essentia" or "Seiendheit"), argues that Nietzsche's thought, just as any other
philosophy since Plato, is metaphysical in nature: "Das Denken Nietzsches ist
gemäss allem Denken des Abendlandes seit Platon Metaphysik," (Heidegger,
II, 257). Contemporary critics, however, often emphasize that Nietzsche does
provide important directions and directives with regard to an alternative conception
of reality. Nietzsche's critique of logic, that of substance, of identity, of
a distinction between thought and being all point at a rejection of the old
metaphysical tradition. His notions of play, of reason and logic as aesthetically
justified and his experiments with language, style and genre all refer to a
world beyond the world of substance.
7. Yet, it is also true that even the most vehement defender
of Nietzsche as a new thinker must remain tentative when it comes down to defining
the practical reality of Nietzsche's antimetaphysical project. Indications how
the new creative human being should live and understand life are at best vague,
and on the overall rather modest in scope. Mihailo Djuric, for instance, in
his Nietzsche und die Metaphysik, speaks of Nietzsche's "creative act" (der schöpferische Akt) as something that Nietzsche opposes to metaphysics,
yet also as something which as a practical reality remains largely "undetermined" (unbestimmt) and "ungraspable" (unfassbar) (148).Underlying the
problem of metaphysical adherence is the difficulty of definition. If going
beyond metaphysics means doing without all distinctions between appearance and
substance, it is questionable whether Nietzsche fully complies with this definition.
Heidegger, for example, considers Nietzsche's truths of will to power and eternal
recurrence as an attempt to arrive at the essence of being. Heidegger argues
that beyond the layer of appearances Nietzsche discovers things as stable and
permanent as the will to create truth or time, or even reality itself to be
circular: "Nietzsche denkt im Gedanken des Willens zur Macht den metaphysischen
Grund der Vollendung der Neuzeit voraus. Im Gedanken des Willens zur Macht vollendet
sich zuvor das metaphysische Denken selbst" (I, 479-80).
8. Other critics emphasize, however, that Nietzsche's concept
of will to power escapes the traditional language of philosophy in that it defies
description and does not refer to any kind of substance or essence, but to a
playful plurality of ever-changing manifestations.Yet, even if this is true,
it might be argued with the same degree of legitimacy that Nietzsche does favour
the life-affirming manifestations of will to power over those which negate,
thus imposing the criterion of life, and ultimately, perhaps, the subjective
truth that to capture the true essence of life it should be lived in a certain
way. And this, strictly speaking, must reflect a metaphysical conception of
reality in which essence may be concealed yet is not absent. Escaping metaphysics,
in the sense of taking being purely as being, appearance without substance,
or existence as a perpetual flow of random events, may be impossible in the
very literal sense of the word. In Zur Genealogie der Moral Nietzsche
speaks of "das souveräne Individuum" as the "ripest fruit" of all humanity,
and as a being freed from conventional morality (das autonome übersittliche
Individuum). The sovereign individual feels the need, deep down inside (ein
stolzes, in allen Muskeln zuckendes Bewusstsein), to lead humanity to its
state of completion (II, 2). Nietzsche states: "Dieser Freigewordene ... wie
sollte er es nicht wissen ... wie ihm, mit dieser Herrschaft über sich,
auch die Herrschaft über die Umstände, über die Natur und alle
willenskürzeren und unzuverlässigeren Kreaturen notwendig in die Hand
gegeben ist? Der 'freie' Mensch ... hat in diesem Besitz auch sein Wertmass"
(II, 2) ["This man who is now free ... how could he remain ignorant of his superiority
... and how could he, with his self-mastery, not realise that he has necessarily
been given mastery over circumstances, over nature and over all creatures with
a less durable and reliable will? The 'free' man, the possessor of a durable,
unbreakable will, thus has his own standard of value" (Nietzsche 1994,
40)]. In fact, our understanding of metaphysics may be largely filtered through
Nietzsche's own interpretation of the metaphysical tradition as characterizing
the pretence of knowledge (Erkenntnis) through logic and discourse. For
Nietzsche, metaphysical investigation in the traditional sense of the word goes
hand in hand with the belief in obtaining essence through the faculties of the
spirit as opposed to those of the body, and from this perspective it is clear
that Nietzsche is not a metaphysician. Nietzsche, it would be hard to deny,
is the philosopher of the body rather than of the conscious mind.
9. Yet, again, if metaphysics is defined in more narrow terms
as being based on the belief that essence exists, and that somehow the fulness
of existence can be sought, acquired or revealed, Nietzsche's escape from metaphysics
may be less evident. If knowledge or essence can be acquired through a more
intuitive type of reason, or through any faculty other than those of the spirit,
would that make Nietzsche someone who escapes or precisely belongs to metaphysics?
Nietzsche's superman may be the playful child sunk into oblivion, yet is it
not this god-sent child, who in Nietzsche's own words is the "ripest fruit" of all, and whose position is the most exemplary and perfect in all humanity,
secretly pledging allegiance to metaphysics in that it constitutes the embodiment
of life that is lived to the fullest? Perhaps one should say that going beyond
metaphysics proper is the radical rejection of any substance, essence or higher
value whatsoever, since only then, when a truer world behind the merely apparent
is being negated, and some sort of essence no longer secretly thought to be
out there, is it possible to speak of something radically opposed to metaphysics.
Irrespective of whether Nietzsche escapes or in some ways still belongs to the
metaphysical tradition, he himself is aware of the difficulty of the task. While
vehemently advocating Dionysian rapture, he informs us at the same time that
this type of liberation from the all too human compulsion of seeking truth behind
illusion is not for the meek and gentle soul. Nietzsche emphasizes often enough
that it takes a special human being who is equipped with a superhuman quality,
as if to illustrate that escaping metaphysics proper belongs to a higher level
of reality, different from the one we, ordinary souls, know.
10. The above theoretical remarks, however tentative, demonstrate
that the metaphysical question is not so easily resolved. Nietzsche's theory
on eternal recurrence, as an example illustrative of this type of complexity,
may defy traditional metaphysical conceptions of how reality is to be defined,
yet it does not abandon the concept of a knowable reality itself. In the following,
I will focus on a number of the arguments used by those who situate Nietzsche
in a tradition that moves away from a metaphysical conception of reality. I
will attempt to demonstrate that these points remain contentious on the basis
of Nietzsche's philosophy itself, and that a certain degree of disagreement
is therefore inevitable. Attributing to Nietzsche the quality of escaping metaphysics
implies making choices where Nietzsche himself has remained silent, unclear,
or ambiguous. In his Nietzsche und die Metaphysik, Djuric concedes that
Nietzsche's concept of play is anything but a fully developed system: "Nietzsche
expressed himself on play with no more clarity and accuracy than on the creative
act. In [his theory of play] there are as many gaps and contradictions; thus
everything remains experimental" (150).
11. Poststructuralist thinkers have generally considered Nietzsche
as escaping metaphysics. Jacques Derrida, for instance, while focussing on texts
that no longer have the pretension of reflecting reality, speaks of the fluidity
of Nietzsche's writing itself as defying the traditional conception of how texts
should be interpreted. For Derrida Nietzsche's writing is set up like a textual
hymen, which can be penetrated yet not possessed, and ultimately presents the
reader in search of meaning with nothing but the reflection of his or her own
metaphysical longing. That is, a longing for essence and truth exactly there
where these entities are absent. The text thus tricks the reader: it plays a
playful game with the mind that wants to possess the true essence of the text.
The concept of play is generally considered as the key by means of which Nietzsche
attempted, if not fully succeeded, to liberate himself from the metaphysical
prison of essence. In the following, I will take up on this element of play
in Nietzsche's writing, and will attempt to demonstrate that with Nietzsche's
notion of play, it is problematic to speak in terms of something that escapes
metaphysics only. Play with Nietzsche may subvert traditional notions of the
usefulness and purpose of life -- Nietzsche's Weltspiel has no Zweck
or Ziel in the religious or scientific sense of these notions -- yet
at the same time it must be acknowledged that Nietzsche speaks of the seriousness
with which one should play the game, and that, consequently, he is no less concerned
with a renewed restoration of metaphysics as with its "deconstruction." That
this restoration or recapturing of a sense of essence is part of a sublimated
type of metaphysical longing is not the issue here. The point is that Nietzsche
was concerned with a metaphysical anchoring of or within play at least as much
as he was with the play itself. Nietzsche explicitly speaks of play in relation
to Unschuld and Ernst as if to metaphysically ground illusion.
Unschuld and Ernst are the two metaphysically sealed doors that
bar the vortex of nihilism, that keep Nietzsche from falling into the void of
playful yet endless illusion. This does not contradict the observation that
Nietzsche attempts to escape metaphysics or that he emphasizes play. What it
does indicate, however, is a difference in emphasis: Nietzsche's definition
of play is that of play as a new type of seriousness. In contrast, poststructuralist
interpreters would rather emphasize Nietzsche's play as a new type of (creative
and free) play.
The Paradigm of the Child
12. Alan D. Schrift quotes in his "ludic alternative to Heidegger's
reading" Zarathustra's speech on the child: "The child is innocence and forgetting,
a new beginning, a game, a self-propelled wheel, a first movement, a sacred
"Yes." For the game of creation, my brothers, a sacred "Yes" is needed: the
spirit now wills its own will, and he who had been lost to the world
now conquers his own world" (68) ["seinen Willen will nun der
Geist, seine Welt gewinnt sich der Weltverlorene" (Zarathustra,
I, 1)]. The point here is not so much the creation of new values as the play
with these values. The child now is the conqueror of, and ruler
over, his own world (to conquer may be too strong a translation of (sich)
gewinnen, which is more to gain or acquire and which seems to me less active),
and it is precisely this superiority over the newly created which constitutes
the element of play. Only the creation acknowledged as creation can generate
a sense of play. The realization of act as artifice is the prerequisite of the
leap towards freedom from metaphysics. And precisely this is the pivotal point
around which turns the question of a ludic alternative to metaphysics. Schrift
states, "the seriousness of Kinderspiel is qualitatively different from the
all-too-heavy seriousness of the metaphysical comforters who preach salvation.
It is the seriousness of the child building castles in the sand, meticulously
creating a world in the full knowledge that the sea may rise up at any moment
and wash this world away" (68). The significance of Schrift's suggestion does
not lie so much in the meticulous creation of the child's new world, as in the
suggestion of the child's realization that the creation exists as creation.
The child realizes that nothing is permanent, since it is in the "full knowledge
that the sea may rise up at any moment and wash [its] world away" (68). The
child's seriousness is a sublimated seriousness -- qualitatively different --
in that the child recognizes the play as play, and its seriousness at the time
of play as the seriousness with which one plays.
13. The image of the child building sand castles on the beach
is powerful and the idea of a transcendent type of playful seriousness is all
too tempting. Djuric, in his chapter on Nietzsche's "Umwandlung der gesamten
menschlichen Tätigkeit in Spiel," focuses on this same point of a playful
seriousness characterized by the player who preserves a certain distance towards
the game. Similarly to Schrift, Djuric suggests as follows: "Eigentlich ist
die erwähnte Hingabe nie vollkommen. Der Spieler bewahrt immer eine Distanz
zu dem, was er tut, da er doch immer irgendwie 'weiss,' dass all dies nur Schein
ist, daß alle seine Spielschritte der Spielwelt als einer imaginären
Realität angehören" (165). Freely translated, we can say that, in
Djuric's view, devotion (Hingabe) to the game is never totally complete,
since Nietzsche's player nevertheless always simply somehow knows that the game
is a game. The bolt on which hinges the promised construct of freedom from this
world of essence is the "irgendwie weiss" mind frame of the player, the "somehow
knowing" that the game is illusion. Yet, precisely here, in the indeterminate
state of the "somehow knowing" lies the weakness of the argument. The quotation
marks, in which appears the player's "knowing," betray the speculative nature
of this knowledge at, and during, play. The inverted commas subvert the argument
that knowing in play is simply knowing that play is play, or simply equal to
any other act of knowing or knowledge. The commas are the old and all too visible
metaphysical cogs that make the anti-metaphysical argument tick. The assertion
of knowing that the world is play is the too-rational approach to something
which escapes reason -- our devotion to the game of life. Giving in to play
requires, if only temporary, a loss of the sense of play as play. We might still
"know," rationally, yet beyond reason, there may be something in us that still,
while playing, does not or should not know that play is play. Schrift's child,
who is fully aware that the castle it has built is going to be swept away, may
be real, but only then when the waves are part of its game. The child is real
only when it has willed the destruction of its own castle. At the end of the
day, the parent of the child -- although Nietzsche's child plays in blessed
solitude with and by himself -- breaks down the metaphysically established illusion
of the game, a game which the child, if only for a moment, has taken for real.
The child's tears mark the awareness of the loss of the essence of the game.
The waves of reality are absent if the child truly wishes to meticulously create
his own world and build castles in the sand. The child's joy in a game is to
take it, in its most literal sense, for real, and not as play.
14. The point here is that the antimetaphysical argument suffers
from metaphysical speculation exactly where play is said to be seen as play,
that is, where the anti-metaphysical pretension of the argument reaches its
highest point. Schrift speaks of the child as being "in the full knowledge"
of play as play, yet the "irgendwie 'weiss'" of Djuric is already considerably
less confident on the question of what exactly one "knows" when play is seen
as play. The knowledge Djuric is referring to might be something different from
conventional knowledge since this knowledge is also somehow, if only temporarily,
a forgetting. Nietzsche speaks here of a "sacred Yes" or the child's "innocence"
in play, but it is rather ironic that Nietzsche should appeal to the old metaphysical
notions of "sacredness," "seriousness," and "innocence" to elevate the argument
into the higher realms of precisely this freedom from metaphysics. This may
have been his intention, of course, but even then it is rather ironic that his
use of the old metaphysical (or even religious) concepts should demonstrate
his very incapacity to even fathom a life beyond metaphysics, or to find an
appropriate terminology to describe it. Djuric's semantically invalidated knowing,
as demonstrated by the inverted commas of "weiss," indicates that knowing might
not be knowing in the conventional sense at all, but rather something one does
not know, or at least does not know how to describe. To know in the sense of
rationally knowing that the game of life is a game seems hardly sufficient in
our attempt to elevate our state of being to a level where essence has become
a playful game. Appealing to reason in something that escapes reason, that is,
our devotion to what we call life, is missing the point. The child's first gasp
of air is grounded in metaphysics: it is a gasp not for breath but for essence
where, always and already, reason is irrelevant. The breath it takes is commanded
by an authority whose realm is beyond any sanctioning of breath as play. The
mother's final push to bring her child into the world is grounded in an essence
that is prior to, without and beyond, knowing.
15. Schrift's powerful image of the child building castles
in the sand is taken from Nietzsche's text, and it is rather significant that
the emphasis in Nietzsche is more on the laws of the game than on the laws of
the child. While for Schrift it is obvious that the child "actively plays
with will to power" instead of being played by it, Nietzsche speaks of a
type of play in which the child is being played with as much as he/she is the
creative observer of the game. Establishing difference here may seem a fastidious
undertaking considering that in this particular section Nietzsche also speaks
of the contemplative nature of the player at play ("der Künstler steht beschaulich über ... dem Kunstwerk"), yet it is important to see
that the difference indicates that the freedom with which the child can choose
to play, or be master of his own game, is considerably reduced. Nietzsche speaks
of play in terms of the "drive to play" (Spieltrieb) and the "need [that]
compels" ("das Bedürfnis zwingt"), thus at least partially subjecting
the child to a force that is more powerful than the child itself, a force that
beyond whatever degree of mastery compels the child to create essence. The play
has ceased to be just play if the child, over and over again, must take play
for real by its own inner urge to seek essence, by its craving to act as if
play is real. Nietzsche states that the child creates essence "according to
inner laws" ("gesetzmäßig und nach inneren Ordnungen"), yet
if there is a set of laws that both compels the child to play and defines the
way in which it has to play, how can it claim to be master of these laws, which
after all govern it rather than vice versa? Nietzsche emphasizes the child's
ever-permanent state of innocence at play ("Ein ewig gleicher Unschuld")
yet innocence refers to more than the lack of a sense of guilt or morality only:
the child is innocent precisely because it allows itself to be fused with the
game, because it lacks, if only for a moment, this sense of play as play. Nietzsche's
innocence is a far cry from the artist's irony: "Und so, wie das Kind und der
Künstler spielt, spielt das ewig lebendige Feuer, baut auf und zerstört,
in Unschuld -- und dieses Spiel spielt der Äon mit sich. Sich verwandelnd
in Wasser und Erde, türmt er wie ein Kind Sandhaufen am Meere, türmt
auf und zertrümmert: von Zeit zu Zeit fängt er das Spiel von neuem
an. Ein Augenblick der Sättigung: dann ergreift ihn von neuem das Bedürfnis,
wie den Künstler zum Schaffen das Bedürfnis zwingt. Nicht Frevelmut,
sondern der immer neu erwachende Spieltrieb ruft andre Welten ins Leben. Das
Kind wirft einmal das Spielzeug weg: bald aber fängt es wieder an in unschuldiger
Laune. Sobald es aber baut, knüpft, fügt und formt es gesetzmässig
und nach inneren Ordnungen" (Die Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter
7).
16. And similarly, just as the child and the artist play,
the eternally living fire plays, builds up and destroys, in innocence -- and
this game the Aeon plays with himself. Transforming himself into water and earth,
like a child he piles heaps of sand by the sea, piles up and demolishes; from
time to time he recommences the game. A moment of satiety, then again desire
seizes him, as desire compels the artist to create. Not wantonness, but the
ever newly awakening impulse to play, calls into life other worlds. The child
throws away his toys; but soon he starts again in an innocent frame of mind.
As soon however as the child builds he connects, joins and forms lawfully and
according to an innate sense of order (see Nietzsche 1964b, 108). The point is not that Nietzsche eliminated or even attempted
to reduce the child's (or the artist's) superiority over the game, thus denying
the possibility of human activity to ultimately transcend its own metaphysical
illusion. What I am arguing, however, is that Nietzsche did emphasize the rigour
of the play's metaphysical power at least as much as he emphasized the child's
power to create and have control over his own game, thus demonstrating a definite
hesitation in cutting a clear break with metaphysics. Emphasis on the sheer
power of illusion, beyond whatever human interference, cannot but reduce the
belief in the child's, artist's or just simply human possibility to break with
metaphysics.
17. The above quotation makes clear that the child does not
simply command the metaphysical power of the game to be unleashed by his own
doing. Nietzsche states that the urge takes hold of the child, thus indicating
the child's submission to his innermost needs, or, in fact, to a rather impersonal
set of needs. Nietzsche uses the poetic "ihn ergreift das Bedürfnis" as
a construct in which the impersonal and faceless "es" (es ergreift
ihn das Bedürfnis) remains implicit and undetermined. Es takes
over, or, in fact, takes "grip" of the child when words no longer suffice in
describing what exactly takes place. In this context, Djuric condemns Eugen
Fink for subjugating Nietzsche's importance of a practice-oriented break from
metaphysics to the importance of a sheer cosmological one, thus emphasizing
the crucial difference between the child instigating play itself and the child
being played with, that is, the difference between a creative type of play and
a play to which one just simply gives in (152-53). While the first is escaping
metaphysics, the second is merely a succumbing to it. Djuric argues that for
Fink Nietzsche's concept of play involves the "world as play" (Weltspiel))
rather than "human beings as players," thus reducing the possibility of humans
to effectively create their own play and preserve superiority over illusion.
But the fact remains that, despite Djuric's effort to retain the human endeavour
at the centre of Nietzsche's philosophy, Nietzsche himself, as demonstrated
in this quote, wittingly or not, has reserved a much less superior and comfortable
position for his playful child than Djuric would like us to believe. An additional difficulty is that speaking of knowing in
terms of forgetting and knowing at the same time suffers from the metaphysical
assumption that knowing at play is just simply like any other type of knowledge
or knowing. Somehow we know that the game of life is a game, even though we
might at times suppress the knowledge that play is play by forgetting and acting
as if we do not know. Yet, as Djuric states, while forgetting, we nonetheless
continue to somehow know. Schrift speaks of a "qualitatively" different type
of knowing ("seriousness") (68). The fact, however, is that this new way of
knowing at play, which is also somehow forgetting, defies the traditional conceptions
of what it is to know. Knowledge at play seems to take place on a subconscious
level rather than anywhere else, and as something which does not coexist with
forgetting but which is rather suppressed or concealed.
18. As I discussed previously, knowing in terms of a rational
assimilation of pieces of knowledge or information according to which action
is initiated, which is the traditional definition of knowing, hardly seems a
sufficient explanation of what goes on when the participant of the game deals
with the game of life. Related to this metaphysical speculation about knowledge
in the game of life is the question of the insufficiency of the words with which
to describe what exactly goes on when one knows during play. As indicated, Schrift
speaks of a qualitatively different seriousness or knowing, yet the question
of why one should still resort to inadequate terminology remains unresolved.
Why refer to seriousness at all if this type of seriousness also incorporates
the lack of it? Nietzsche speaks of the child's Ernst and Unschuld,
and its sacred pledge to life, yet the falling back upon the old metaphysical
definitions of how to approach life must indicate, beyond whatever expression
of venomous irony, the impossibility to ultimately make a distinction between
the efforts of the naive believer and the bad faith of the one claiming to somehow
know.
Nietzsche's Instinctive Knowledge
19. We know that Nietzsche was thinking in terms of an "instinctive"
knowledge. The "irgendwie weiss" of Djuric and the "full knowledge" of Schrift
refer to Nietzsche's "internalized knowledge" (sich einverleibt[es] Wissen).
Nietzsche's awareness of play as play turns away from reason in that it is an
embodied knowledge, an instinct (Instinkt), a drive (Trieb) (quoted
in Fröhliche Wissenschaft 11). Yet, we should pay attention to the
fact that the problem of metaphysical speculation remains. Nietzsche, although
perhaps not explicitly, makes a distinction between knowledge of the spirit
and that of the body, thus establishing a qualitative distinction between the
two in favour of the latter. Yet, as Nietzsche at other times has stated himself,
both the distinction and the qualitative differentiation between body and spirit
are based on a false metaphysical premise. In a section on the prevalence of
the body in Also Sprach Zarathustra, for instance, Nietzsche argues "Leib
bin ich ganz und gar, und Nichts ausserdem, und Seele ist nur ein Wort für
ein Etwas am Leibe" (I, 39) ["body am I entirely, and nothing else; and soul
is only a word for something about the body" (Kaufmann 34)]. We are nothing
but body, and the soul is only a word. To speak of bodily knowledge in terms
of knowledge is making the false metaphysical assumption that bodily knowledge
is still somehow knowledge, though different from a rational type. In the final
analysis, however, there can only exist one type of knowledge for human beings
-- the knowledge of the conscious mind, the knowledge shaped by words, in Nietzsche's
terminology: das Wissen, die Vernunft, das vernünftige Denken, etc.). Speaking
of the subconscious knowledge of the drives is in itself an impossibility, since
the drives and the subconsciousness are beyond and outside language and consciousness.
True, language may define the unconscious in terms of knowledge, yet this is,
strictly speaking, as Nietzsche has indicated himself, merely appropriating
the unfathomable.
20. In a section entitled "to experience and to invent" Nietzsche
states that consciousness is the interpretation of unknown physiological processes,
and that to experience is to invent ("Erleben ist ein Erdichten"): "all unser
sogenanntes Bewusstsein [ist] ein mehr oder weniger phantastischer Kommentar
über einen ungewussten, vielleicht unwissbaren, aber gefühlten Text" (Morgenröte 119) ["all our so-called consciousness is a more or
less fantastic commentary on an unknown, perhaps unknowable, but felt text"
(Clark and Leiter 120)]. Nietzsche also argues that drives do not think, simply
because they cannot think: "Because all drives are unintelligent, "usefulness" ("Nützlichkeit") is of no importance to them" (qtd in Colli and
Montinari X, 342). Knowledge in order to be knowledge is always already
rational, converted into language, transformed into familiar imagery, summoned
onto the plane of consciousness. In one of his unpublished notes, Nietzsche
argues that human beings stop thinking when they try to think beyond language
("im sprachlichen Zwange") (Aus dem Nachlaß der Achtzigerjahre
qtd. in Schlechta 862). Human beings cannot know what lies
beyond the act of knowing. This means that Nietzsche's internalized knowledge
is no knowledge, unless defined as such -- and perhaps inevitably distorted
-- on a purely rational, linguistic, or epistemological level. Instincts and
drives may exist, yet speaking in terms of instinctual knowledge must inevitably
suffer from the human need to domesticate a force over which, literally speaking,
human beings have no say. This force defies, by its very nature, the boundaries
of human definition.
21. Nietzsche's inconsistency here may be said to reflect
the complexity of the metaphysical question. For Nietzsche the task is to somehow
make the child's knowledge at play more instinctive, and considering Nietzsche's
impatience with reason we understand why. Yet, once again, making knowledge
instinctive is impossible, unless the knowledge is no real knowledge but already
somehow instinct or drive. Human beings cling to life, yet strictly speaking
we do not know what it is that makes us cling to life. As Nietzsche states himself,
to find a rationale may be possible, yet the rationale is made up of language,
and language is a collection of fictions with which to grasp a reality we cannot
know. We may be said, then, to understand life as play, to breathe to play,
to breathe as play, to playfully breathe. Yet, understanding life as play is
grounded in reason, and it is Nietzsche himself who denounces the faculty of
the mind to approach something as unfathomable as the simple act of living or
breathing. Living seems to be foregrounded in metaphysics and essence in that
it compels human beings to move, ever forward, backward, create, destroy, struggle,
believe and breathe, as if it all makes sense, as if there were no end to our
days. My remarks here are not intended to triumphantly indicate Nietzsche's
inconsistency, even if on a metaphysical level. Dismissing Nietzsche and pointing
out inconsistency on the basis of a few carefully selected quotes would be missing
the point. My intention in this study has been to primarily indicate that the
metaphysical question with Nietzsche is not so easily resolved. Deciding on
Nietzsche's successful transcendence of metaphysics, as Djuric argues, in his
well-documented study, means making decisions where Nietzsche remains ambiguous
or incomplete. It comes as no surprise that interpreting Nietzsche's text involves
making choices, just like interpreting any other text. Yet, with Nietzsche the
stakes are high and the questions on which decisions are to be made remarkably
complex. We have seen that deciding on the metaphysical question is touching
on something very basic and human. To decide on the successful transcendence
of metaphysics is to be faced with the inevitable and perhaps unresolvable question
of having to use an instrument which is grounded in metaphysics: our consciousness
and our language.
22. I have attempted to demonstrate that in his texts about
the playful child -- a premise of poststructuralist paradigm -- Nietzsche remains
more ambiguous and tentative than some of his critics would have us believe.
The texts demonstrate that escaping metaphysics proper is problematic in that
the child is not always superior to the game, which is the condition of a successful
transcendence. Nietzsche states that inner laws compel the child to play and
to fuse with the game no less than that the child freely creates. I have attempted
to demonstrate as well that the premise of the child "somehow knowing" (Djuric)
that all is nothing but play is based on speculation if one continues to define
this somehow knowing in terms of knowledge. This may appear a little vague,
yet what I am trying to argue here is that considering play as play in the game
of life can hardly be a sufficient criterion to escape metaphysics when this
knowledge plays on a rational level only. Nietzsche's attempt to make this knowledge
somehow instinctive proves that this has been a contentious point for Nietzsche
also. Escaping metaphysics on a practical level is surely not the all too rational
avowal of just claiming to consider life as play. That is merely bad faith.
"fully knowing" (Schrift) that life is illusion to the extent of fully knowing
what life is all about is problematic, in Nietzsche's view also: "Wir haben
eben gar kein Organ für das Erkennen, für die 'Wahrheit': wir
'wissen' (oder glauben oder bilden uns ein) gerade so viel, als es im Interesse
der Menschen-Herde, der Gattung, nützlich sein mag" (Die
fröhliche Wissenschaft 354) ["Indeed, we have not any organ at all
for knowing, or for "truth": we "know" (or believe, or fancy) just as
much as may be of use in the interest of the human herd, the species" (Nietzsche 1964a, 300)]. We only know as much as we ought to know for our own
well-being.
23. Eugen Fink states that "das dionysische Gipfelglück
des Menschen liegt in der panischen Erfahrung, die uns die Nichtigkeit aller
individuierten Gestalten kundgibt" (188). A free yet accurate translation would
be: the most intense joy lies in our panic-stricken awareness of life as it
is. This awareness may occur at times, to be sure. Yet, my argument has been
that in order to live human beings must rather suppress than prolong this panic-stricken
sentiment. That, in fact, living life itself is conditioned, over and over again,
by the suppressing of its more terrifying realities. Ultimately, my argument
is also simply that human beings are steeped in metaphysics, and that a sense
of metaphysics or essence is the condition for all human life. Related to this
is the difficulty of language, and the fact that language is perhaps inescapably
metaphysical. And here I conclude with a quote. In one of the stories of Jorge
Luis Borges's Ficciones (these precious testimonies to the complexities
of the human mind), the author speaks of his stammering acquaintance with "Funes
the memorious," this "precursor of the supermen," this "vernacular and rustic
Zarathustra" (59), this mannish boy gifted and cursed with the means to see
and feel the world as it is (the title of the story is "Funes el memorioso"
and Borges describes it as a metaphor for insomnia): "[Ireneo Funes] was ...
almost incapable of ideas of a general, Platonic sort. Not only was it difficult
for him to comprehend that the generic symbol dog embraces so many unlike
individuals of diverse size and form; it bothered him that the dog at three
fourteen (seen from the side) should have the same name as the dog at three
fifteen (seen from the front). His own face in the mirror, his own hands, surprised
him every time he saw them. ... Funes could continuously discern the tranquil
advances of corruption, of decay, of fatigue. He could note the progress of
death, of dampness. He was the solitary and lucid spectator of a multiform,
instantaneous and almost intolerably precise world" (65). But the author also states that "[Funes] was not very
capable of thought. To think is to forget differences, generalize, make abstractions"
(66). I would like to argue with Borges' position that to think is to forget.
Perhaps one "somehow knows," yet the knowledge does not interfere: thus we may
know yet do not realize, we may argue and reason, yet, because of the urge to
establish a set of metaphysical certainties, we cannot feel the intensity of
what, who and where we are: "Ireneo was nineteen years old ...; he seemed to
me as monumental as bronze, more ancient than Egypt, older than the prophecies
and the pyramids. I thought that each of my words (that each of my movements)
would persist in his implacable memory; I was benumbed by the fear of multiplying
useless gestures" (66).
Works Cited
Colli, G., and M. Montinari, eds. Friedrich Nietzsche: Sämtliche
Werke. München: Deutscher Taschenbuch, 1988.
Schlechta, K. Friedrich Nietzsche: Werke. München: Hanser
Verlag, 1965.
Allison, David B., ed. The New Nietzsche: Contemporary Styles of Interpretation.
New York: Dell, 1977.
Berger, Hermann. Wat is Metafysica? Een studie over transcendentie. Assen:
Van Gorcum, 1993.
Borges, Jorge Luis. "Funes the Memorious." Labyrinths: Selected Stories amd
Other Writings. Ed. Donald A. Yates and James E. Irby. Trans. James Irby.
New York: Modern Library, 1983.
Djuric, Mihailo. Nietzsche und die Metaphysik. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1985.
Fink, E. Nietzsches Philosophie. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1960.
Heidegger, Martin. Nietzsche (I & II). Pfullingen: Neske,
1961.
Koelb, C., ed. Nietzsche as Postmodernist: Essays pro and contra. Albany:
State U of New York P, 1990.
Mann, Thomas. Nietzsches Philosophie im Lichte unserer Erfahrung. Frankfurt:
Suhrkamp, 1948.
Nietzsche, F. The Joyful Wisdom. Trans. Thomas Common. New York: Russell
and Russell, 1964a.
Nietzsche, F. "Philosophy during the Tragic Age of the Greeks." Early Greek
Philosophy. Trans. Maximilian A. Mügge. New York: Russell and Russell,
1964b.
Nietzsche, F. On the Genealogy of Morality. Ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson.
Trans. Carol Diethe. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994.
Nietzsche, F. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York:
The Modern Library, 1995.
Nietzsche, F. Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality. Ed. Maudemarie
Clark and Brian Leiter. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1997.
Schrift, Alan D. Nietzsche and the Question of Interpretation: Between Hermeneutics
and Deconstruction. London: Routledge, 1990.
to top of page
CLCWeb: Comparative
Literature and Culture: A WWWeb Journal ISSN 1481-4374
CLCWeb Library of Research and Information ...
CLCWeb Contents 1.3 (June
1999)
<http://clcwebjournal.lib.purdue.edu/clcweb99-3/welfing99.html> © Purdue
University Press